jcreed blog > A Postulate for Internalized Parametricity
A Postulate for Internalized Parametricity
Update! Everything Below Is Perhaps Bunk! Evan Cavallo shrewdly sniffed out the fact that the below idea runs into a gap if you try to show free theorems
for any nontrivial polymorphic type where the type variable occurs negatively.
Maybe it can be repaired somehow? Or quite possibly I'm stumbling down the path towards reinventing the POPL'24 paper cited below. I'm having fun either way.
I had the follow-up thought about the previous post, and though I have no particular confidence
that it is consistent and/or novel, I thought I'd write it down anyways.
Suppose we postulate first of all that there is a "bridge interval"
(to borrow a term of this paper, which I have not fully digested, and which may for all I know do everything I'm doing here but better) type I that has two known points
i0,i1:I.
From any type family V:I→Set we can derive a (binary, proof-relevant) relation. I'm
going to use record notation and say the type of relations is
Rel:={A0:Set,A1:Set,R:Set,π0:R→A0,π1:R→A1}
Then we can make some definitions
A0:(V:I→Set)→Set | A0 V=V i0 |
A1:(V:I→Set)→Set | A1 V=V i1 |
R:(V:I→Set)→Set | R V=(i:I)→V i |
π0:(V:I→Set)→R V→A0 V | π0 V r=r i0 |
π1:(V:I→Set)→R V→A1 V | π1 V r=r i1 |
And bundle all this up as
mkr:(I→Set)→Rel
mkr V={
A0=A0 V, A1=A1 V,R=R V,π0=π0 V, π1=π1 V
}
The set A0 is the fiber over i0, the set A1 is the fiber over i1,
and the R consists of the global elements of the indexed set V.
Each global element can be instantiated to give an element of A0 or A1,
so we really do have a span across A0,A1.
The Postulate
Now consider what happens if we postulate that
mkr is an equivalence
That is, mkr has some inverse
mkr−1:Rel→I→Set
and so every relation arises as the mkr of some I→Set.
Preserving Relations
Next we we want to observe that whenever we have V,W:I→Set,
every map of the form
h:(i:I)→V i→W i
induces a relation-preserving map.
Namely, the map
λm.λi.h i (m i):((i:I)→V I)→((i:I)→W I)
goes by definition also R V→R W, and can be seen to commute
with the maps
h i0:V i0→W i0=A0 V→A0 W
h i1:V i1→W i1=A1 V→A1 W
In other words, we have a commutative diagram
or equivalently by definition,
Parametricity
Suppose we'd like to show the canonical example free theorem that
j:(A:Set)→A→A
must be the identity function.
We can do this by showing that j appropriately commutes with any
function f:A→B, i.e. by showing
(f:A→B)→f∘j A=j B∘f(*)
because if that were true, then for any a:A we could set f to
K a, the constantly-a function A→A, and find that
(a:A)→Ka∘j A=j A∘K a
and therefore
(a:A)→a=j A a
so j would be the identity function.
Now to show (*), define ρ:Rel to be the underyling relation
of the function f, i.e.
ρ={A0=A, A1=B, R=(a:A)(b:B)×f a≡b,
π0⟨a,b,q⟩=a, π1⟨a,b,q⟩=b}
What happens when
we apply j to the type mkr−1 ρ i for various i:I?
We obtain
h=λi.j (mkr−1 ρ i):(i:I)→mkr−1 ρ i→mkr−1 ρ i
This is an example of an h from the previous section about preserving relations!
So we obtain a commutative diagram, where the top and bottom horizontal maps
are h i0 and h i1. But in particular our h i0 is equal to
j (mkr−1 ρ i0)=j (A0 (mkr−1 ρ))
=j ((mkr(mkr−1 ρ)).A0)
=j (ρ.A0)
=j A
and likewise h i1=j B
So what we have is a commutative diagram
which can be massaged into
as required.